The Foundations of Science: Science and Hypothesis, The Value of Science, Science and Method. Henri Poincare

Читать онлайн.
Название The Foundations of Science: Science and Hypothesis, The Value of Science, Science and Method
Автор произведения Henri Poincare
Жанр Документальная литература
Серия
Издательство Документальная литература
Год выпуска 0
isbn 4057664651143



Скачать книгу

to make to reach that object; and one may not say that to represent to oneself these movements, it is necessary to project the movements themselves in space and that the notion of space must, consequently, pre-exist.

      When I say that we represent to ourselves these movements, I mean only that we represent to ourselves the muscular sensations which accompany them and which have no geometric character whatever, which consequently do not at all imply the preexistence of the notion of space.

      Change of State and Change of Position.—But, it will be said, if the idea of geometric space is not imposed upon our mind, and if, on the other hand, none of our sensations can furnish it, how could it have come into existence?

      This is what we have now to examine, and it will take some time, but I can summarize in a few words the attempt at explanation that I am about to develop.

      None of our sensations, isolated, could have conducted us to the idea of space; we are led to it only in studying the laws, according to which these sensations succeed each other.

      We see first that our impressions are subject to change; but among the changes we ascertain we are soon led to make a distinction.

      At one time we say that the objects which cause these impressions have changed state, at another time that they have changed position, that they have only been displaced.

      Whether an object changes its state or merely its position, this is always translated for us in the same manner: by a modification in an aggregate of impressions.

      How then could we have been led to distinguish between the two? It is easy to account for. If there has only been a change of position, we can restore the primitive aggregate of impressions by making movements which replace us opposite the mobile object in the same relative situation. We thus correct the modification that happened and we reestablish the initial state by an inverse modification.

      If it is a question of sight, for example, and if an object changes its place before our eye, we can 'follow it with the eye' and maintain its image on the same point of the retina by appropriate movements of the eyeball.

      These movements we are conscious of because they are voluntary and because they are accompanied by muscular sensations, but that does not mean that we represent them to ourselves in geometric space.

      So what characterizes change of position, what distinguishes it from change of state, is that it can always be corrected in this way.

      It may therefore happen that we pass from the totality of impressions A to the totality B in two different ways:

      1º Involuntarily and without experiencing muscular sensations; this happens when it is the object which changes place;

      2º Voluntarily and with muscular sensations; this happens when the object is motionless, but we move so that the object has relative motion with reference to us.

      If this be so, the passage from the totality A to the totality B is only a change of position.

      It follows from this that sight and touch could not have given us the notion of space without the aid of the 'muscular sense.'

      Not only could this notion not be derived from a single sensation or even from a series of sensations, but what is more, an immobile being could never have acquired it, since, not being able to correct by his movements the effects of the changes of position of exterior objects, he would have had no reason whatever to distinguish them from changes of state. Just as little could he have acquired it if his motions had not been voluntary or were unaccompanied by any sensations.

      Conditions of Compensation.—How is a like compensation possible, of such sort that two changes, otherwise independent of each other, reciprocally correct each other?

      A mind already familiar with geometry would reason as follows: Evidently, if there is to be compensation, the various parts of the external object, on the one hand, and the various sense organs, on the other hand, must be in the same relative position after the double change. And, for that to be the case, the various parts of the external object must likewise have retained in reference to each other the same relative position, and the same must be true of the various parts of our body in regard to each other.

      In other words, the external object, in the first change, must be displaced as is a rigid solid, and so must it be with the whole of our body in the second change which corrects the first.

      Under these conditions, compensation may take place.

      But we who as yet know nothing of geometry, since for us the notion of space is not yet formed, we can not reason thus, we can not foresee a priori whether compensation is possible. But experience teaches us that it sometimes happens, and it is from this experimental fact that we start to distinguish changes of state from changes of position.

      Solid Bodies and Geometry.—Among surrounding objects there are some which frequently undergo displacements susceptible of being thus corrected by a correlative movement of our own body; these are the solid bodies. The other objects, whose form is variable, only exceptionally undergo like displacements (change of position without change of form). When a body changes its place and its shape, we can no longer, by appropriate movements, bring back our sense-organs into the same relative situation with regard to this body; consequently we can no longer reestablish the primitive totality of impressions.

      It is only later, and as a consequence of new experiences, that we learn how to decompose the bodies of variable form into smaller elements, such that each is displaced almost in accordance with the same laws as solid bodies. Thus we distinguish 'deformations' from other changes of state; in these deformations, each element undergoes a mere change of position, which can be corrected, but the modification undergone by the aggregate is more profound and is no longer susceptible of correction by a correlative movement.

      Such a notion is already very complex and must have been relatively late in appearing; moreover it could not have arisen if the observation of solid bodies had not already taught us to distinguish changes of position.

      Therefore, if there were no solid bodies in nature, there would be no geometry.

      Another remark also deserves a moment's attention. Suppose a solid body to occupy successively the positions α and β; in its first position, it will produce on us the totality of impressions A, and in its second position the totality of impressions B. Let there be now a second solid body, having qualities entirely different from the first, for example, a different color. Suppose it to pass from the position α, where it gives us the totality of impressions , to the position β, where it gives the totality of impressions .

      In general, the totality A will have nothing in common with the totality , nor the totality B with the totality . The transition from the totality A to the totality B and that from the totality to the totality are therefore two changes which in themselves have in general nothing in common.

      And yet we regard these two changes both as displacements and, furthermore, we consider them as the same displacement. How can that be?

      It is simply because they can both be corrected by the same correlative movement of our body.

      'Correlative movement' therefore constitutes the sole connection between two phenomena which otherwise we never should have dreamt of likening.

      On the other hand, our body, thanks to the number of its articulations and muscles, may make a multitude of different movements; but all are not capable of 'correcting' a modification of external objects; only those will be capable of it in which our whole body, or at least all those of our sense-organs which come into play, are displaced as a whole, that is, without their relative positions varying, or in the fashion of a solid body.

      To summarize:

      1º We are led at first to distinguish two categories of phenomena:

      Some, involuntary, unaccompanied