Название | Education in a Postfactual World |
---|---|
Автор произведения | Patrick M. Whitehead |
Жанр | Прочая образовательная литература |
Серия | |
Издательство | Прочая образовательная литература |
Год выпуска | 0 |
isbn | 9781627346863 |
This book will examine some of the advantages for the assumption that modernity was the last amendment to science. But above all, it is an attempt to reverse the piece of ontological legislation that was passed by the Vienna Circle in 1924. To be fair, the legislation itself merely echoed the consensus of scientists and philosophers at the time, but this little event gives the travesty a time and place. The travesty is simple, and it frames the structure of what Husserl called The Crisis of European Sciences; it will also frame the structure of this book.
The travesty may be understood as follows: nature is made of processes and things. Processes are complicated systems that are constantly changing and are thus difficult to know in fact. Processes must understand how they work. Things are simple and easy to know in fact because it is believed that they are unchanging. The Vienna Circle eliminated “processes” from the list, leaving only things. The consequences of this are lived by each of us every day.
Before heading into the fields of education, philosophy, and science, I describe what happens when it becomes customary to replace processes with things. Because it is easier to reduce the world to facts about the world, replacing processes with things is commonplace. This is called abstractification. I have borrowed this term from Erich Fromm in his book Sane Society. Fromm, a Marxist scholar and practicing psychoanalyst, describes the psychopathology that necessarily accompanies capitalism. Like Marx, Fromm argues that men and women have become alienated from their own experience, and that it has become perfectly normal to treat yourself and others as though they are things. Fromm calls this psychopathological; Husserl calls this a crisis; I’m simply calling your attention to it.
* * *
This book is really about abstractification, but the word was too cumbersome for a title. You might recognize the root word in there: abstract or abstraction. If you noticed this then you’re on the right track; you defied the odds and managed to learn something despite all of your years of schooling. If in the end you understand the difference between abstraction and abstractification, then you will be able to talk about another person as a thing without forgetting that they are more than this. Indeed, if you understand this, then you can anticipate the chapters that come.
Abstraction is an instance of referring to a process as a thing. For instance, I might call my 2005 AWD Toaster a car. In the South, it’s called a truck. My car has a unique history with me; I have many concrete experiences with it. To understand what this car is to me, you will have to investigate each of these concrete experiences which includes the many trips from Georgia to Michigan, the countless times I have left the windows down before a flash-flood, and the stratified layers of dirt, clay, mud, and grass left there by trail-running shoes. When I call it “the orange car,” I place it into an abstract category that includes a whole assortment of others. You see, this category says nothing of the concrete experiences just mentioned. The abstraction is helpful in a parking lot because you would have some difficulty finding the “one that I have driven back and forth between Georgia and Michigan”; when I say it is “the orange car” then finding it in a parking lot is much easier. You and I understand that I don’t simply mean “the orange car,” but that I still have in mind the many concrete experiences when I talk about my car. It is just that the abstraction is a useful placeholder for now.
Abstractification occurs when I forget that the abstraction is actually just a placeholder. Abstractification is what I do when I replace the concrete experience with the placeholder. For my 2005 AWD Orange Toaster, this would mean replacing all of my experiences with the single thing—“the orange car.” We had just agreed that learning that my car is orange is helpful for finding it in a parking lot, but that it leaves a lot out—most importantly, it leaves out any concrete experience or anything that makes it my car. That is, if you also drive an “orange car” then you know what it’s like to drive my Toaster. Abstractification leaves the concrete out permanently. Furthermore, it assumes that every experience can be understood in terms of things. It assumes that we are nothing but collections of things.
Interestingly enough, the terms “abstraction” and “concretion” seem to have gotten swapped. For instance, when I tell somebody that I study lived experience (that is, concrete experiences), I am often met with the reply “oh that’s too abstract for me.” I never quite know how to respond to this. I can only imagine that it has become unfamiliar to pay attention to one’s experience. Experience has been replaced by the procedure of identifying experiences as things (and then placing them into categories, and so on). Rather than feeling alien to the categories that are used to define us “professor,” “student,” “heterosexual,” “white,” and so on, we feel alien to our own experiences. “Professor” does not capture who I am as a person, and we shouldn’t expect it to. “What does it mean to you to be a professor?” Such a question should be followed by a pause of uncertainty. The uncertainty highlights the complexity (or unfamiliarity) of concrete experience. Instead we say, “I don’t know what that means; that’s too abstract for me.” However, we are often perfectly satisfied with a basic categorization when we meet someone; it is easier to think about them as a thing and not as a complicated process.
We buy coffee from the barista at the shop on the corner. We forget that the barista is a person with a unique biography, and that on this particular day our path crossed with theirs. At that moment, the manifestation of their being is in tandem with the actualization of your own.1 “But that’s too abstract for me.” No, “concrete” is the word that troubles you. The situation I am asking you to consider is “too concrete for you.” This means that you are uncomfortable when asked to participate in your experience. Indeed, we find such an examination of, or participation in, our own experience to be alienating: we are unfamiliar with that which is most personal to us. That’s tragic.
Finally, it is not an accident that Erich Fromm has supplied us with this term. Fromm used the theories of Karl Marx to develop his approach to clinical psychology. Indeed, his construction of the term “abstractification” can be understood within the framework of a Marxist critique of capitalism. A brief foray into this will follow as a first example of abstractification—the abstractification of money. Before getting to that, I will allow Fromm (1990) to introduce the term as he has engineered it:
In order to understand the abstractification process in modern man, we must first consider the ambiguous function of abstraction in general. It is obvious that abstractions in themselves are not a modern phenomenon. In fact, an increasing ability to form abstractions is characteristic of the cultural development of the human race. If I speak of “a table,” I am using an abstraction; I am referring, not to a specific table in its full concreteness, but to the genus “table” which comprises all possible concrete tables. If I speak of “a man” I am not speaking of this or that person, in his concreteness and uniqueness, but of the genus “man,” which comprises all individual persons. (113–114)
To review what has been meant by “abstraction” and “concretion,” let me summarize: Fromm explains that the process of moving from the specific instance (concrete) to the general case (abstract) is an instance of abstraction.
Try this exercise: Draw a square on the margin of this page. Is it a square? Chances are that the concrete figure that you have drawn is actually no square at all. The side-lengths probably aren’t all equal, and the angles probably aren’t exactly 90-degrees. But we can fit it into the category nonetheless. “Square” is an abstraction of the concrete “whatever” you’ve just drawn (or imagined because there wasn’t a pen handy). The terms “abstraction” and “concretion” come from the categorizing procedures of logic. There will be more spoken on the system of logic in the chapters that follow. Now back to Fromm’s quote. He alludes to the biological classification system with examples of the terms genus and species. You are a person. Not many people know you very