Название | A Companion to Arthur C. Danto |
---|---|
Автор произведения | Группа авторов |
Жанр | Афоризмы и цитаты |
Серия | |
Издательство | Афоризмы и цитаты |
Год выпуска | 0 |
isbn | 9781119154235 |
The quickest route to seeing the normative point of the normative analysis of agent identity lies in the case of group agency. Insofar as a group of human beings is able to reason and act as one, it generally manages this by coordinating its efforts through overt discussion. But these discussions are not carried out in the spirit of arguing, or other techniques of persuasion that distinct agents exert over one another from their separate points of view. They are carried out rather in the spirit of working out what it would be best to think and do in the light of a body of pooled deliberative considerations. One example I often use in order to illustrate this highlights the difference between a philosophy department that “decides” matters by arguing and then voting, vs. a philosophy department that truly deliberates, by working out the all-things-considered significance of all of the considerations that have been brought to the table to consider. In the latter case, the discussions that occur in a department meeting have the same normative form that we find in the silent deliberations of an individual agent of human size: one thing is said, and the next thing that is said registers something that rationally follows from what is said, and that next thing is a step in further discussion that continues in the same spirit of working out what follows from the entire pooled set of deliberative considerations. This pooled set then constitutes the single point of view from which the philosophy department reasons and acts as one. Obviously, the boundaries of this point of view are not metaphysically given but are forged through effort and will.
According to the normative analysis, this is always true, no matter what boundaries get set. That is, the existence of an individual agent with its own point of view is always a product of effort and will. It follows that a human being is not born as an individual agent with a single, first-person point of view in the normative sense. A human being becomes the site of such a single point of view when it becomes the site of commitment to reasoning and acting as one within the biological boundaries of its life. But human lives may support other commitments as well – commitments to reasoning and acting as one within less than that whole human life, as well as across many human lives.
It might seem paradoxical to say that agents are products of effort and will: how can there be any such effort and will unless there is an agent already there to exert it? But there is no paradox, if we allow that the life of an agent consists in the intentional activities – the thinkings and doings – through which its life is constituted. It is the thinkings and doings that do the constituting work so as to yield a recognizable individual who reasons and acts as one. This, in my view, is the correct interpretation of, and the deep truth in, the claim that agents are self-constituting. The life of an individual agent just is its rational activities, which are directed at meeting the normative requirements that define individual rationality.
The boundaries that circumscribe a given agent’s life are always forged for reasons. These reasons concern the worth of what can be done by constituting a particular agent, with its own point of view, within those particular boundaries. It is obvious that what a group agent like a philosophy department can do, is not the same as what an agent of human size can do, which in turn is not the same as what can be done by multiple agents within a human life. This is another respect in which the normative analysis of agent identity is thoroughgoingly normative – not only does it say that no other metaphysical condition is required for the existence of an agent, besides the presence of a commitment to meeting the requirements that define individual rationality within a given boundary; but furthermore, it says that the very reasons for an agent’s existence are likewise normative, insofar as they have to do with the fact that reasoning and acting as one within that given boundary makes it possible to do something worth doing.
What, then, does the agent’s body emerge to be on the normative analysis of agent identity? To some extent, we can model it on Danto’s definition of an agent’s body, as that over which it exerts direct intentional control by performing basic actions, only we must substitute the normative definition of an agent’s powers that I offered above in my friendly amendment to Danto and Levi. What an agent can do in this normative sense is what the agent believes it will do if it recognizes reasons to do it. The agent’s body then emerges to be the domain of intentional control that is referenced by such first-person conditional beliefs about its own powers. Note that, just as the very existence of an agent is not a metaphysical given according to the normative analysis but a product of effort and will, the same holds for an agent’s body. This may seem paradoxical in just the way that the idea of self-constitution may seem paradoxical. But the point should be easy to see if we consider what lies within the power of a philosophy department to do, and how a particular domain of intentional control comes to be. This point about self-constitution makes for a sharp contrast with Danto’s view, on which an agent’s repertoire of basic actions is a gift. Nevertheless, the normative analysis does yield a distinction between the me and the not-me: the me that acts upon the world will incorporate whatever I take to be under my intentional control – though, intuitively, this might include a great many things that Danto would place on the worldly side of the me/not-me divide.
References
1 Bilgrami, Akeel. 2012. Self-Knowledge and Resentment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
2 Danto, Arthur C. 1965. “Basic Actions.” American Philosophical Quarterly 2(2): 141–8.
3 Levi, Isaac. 1985. Hard Choices. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
4 Rovane, Carol. 1998. Bounds of Agency. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Конец ознакомительного фрагмента.
Текст предоставлен ООО «ЛитРес».
Прочитайте эту книгу целиком, купив полную легальную версию на ЛитРес.
Безопасно оплатить книгу можно банковской картой Visa, MasterCard, Maestro, со счета мобильного телефона, с платежного терминала, в салоне МТС или Связной, через PayPal, WebMoney, Яндекс.Деньги, QIWI Кошелек, бонусными картами или другим удобным Вам способом.