A Companion to Arthur C. Danto. Группа авторов

Читать онлайн.
Название A Companion to Arthur C. Danto
Автор произведения Группа авторов
Жанр Афоризмы и цитаты
Серия
Издательство Афоризмы и цитаты
Год выпуска 0
isbn 9781119154235



Скачать книгу

use of “galleries [Hospitals?] of indiscernibles,” comparable to Danto’s gallery for art. Here is a well-known case: Someone is attached to a life support machine. If the person’s doctor unplugs him, it is said by many to be a case of terminating treatment that constitutes a letting die. By contrast, if the person’s “greedy nephew” unplugs him, in a “perceptually indiscernible” way with perceptually indiscernible consequences (the uncle dies), it is said by many to be a killing.

      Though it is imagined that the doctor and the nephew engage in the same exact movements, this is not necessary in order for the issue to arise of whether the two acts are of the same type (killing or letting die). This is because no one would take seriously the idea that, for example, a difference in the curve made by the doctor’s hand from the curve made by the nephew’s hand could be relevant to whether one act was a letting die and the other a killing. The same could be true of Danto’s examples. Suppose that each of his red canvases had a slightly different tiny dot in its right corner. The canvases would be discernible, but it would not be any easier to determine by perceptual means what was an artwork from what was not. However, once one decides (by reference to nonperceptual factors such as aboutness etc.) which canvases are artworks, the dots could help avoid confusing the artwork with the non-artwork.

      It has been argued that factors not perceptible in the unplugging action (such as who owns the life support machine, who has the rights to control the machine, etc.) could make the physically identical act (and consequences) of pulling the plug into either a killing or instead a letting die. For example, if a doctor exercising legitimate control over the machine attaches someone to it and then while still retaining legitimate control over its use unplugs the person, he could be letting the man die in withdrawing life support as much as he would be letting him die if he did not start the life support machine to begin with. By contrast, if the nephew pulls the plug on the machine, assuming that he has no right to decide whether to let others use it, he will have interfered with a machine he has no right to control, and this results in someone’s death. This may make what he does a killing. The view that factors not perceptible in an act can determine whether the act is a killing or a letting die is analogous to Danto’s view that something not perceptible in a physical object can determine whether something is art.

      The most famous thought experiments in ethics are not concerned with determining into which conceptual category an act falls, but with whether an act is permissible and why. For example, many variations on one basic Trolley Problem Case are thought experiments about whether and why what is assumed to be a killing (turning the trolley from killing five people to killing one other person) is permissible when one could instead do what is assumed to be a letting die (as when a bystander does not turn the trolley away from hitting five people thereby letting them die so as not to kill one other person). In philosophy of art, a comparable question is whether what had been determined to be an artwork is at least minimally good, comparable to “permissible” in morality. A second question is what makes or explains why the minimally good work of art is good. Other thought experiments in ethics are concerned with whether an act of one type is morally equivalent to or morally different from an act of another type and why. A famous example is whether killing is per se morally worse than letting die per se. The comparable questions in philosophy of art might be whether one type of artwork (e.g., still life) has less merit per se than another type (e.g., landscape) and why.

      None of Danto’s thought experiments that I have described is concerned with these comparable questions about the merit of works of art. Hence, use of thought experiments in ethics is often unlike the use of thought experiments in Danto’s work. One question is whether thought experiments could be used in art analogous to the way they are used in ethics to deal with (im)permissibility or moral (in)equivalence and the reasons for it. Another question is how the use of these thought experiments in ethics bears on the issue raised by Wollheim of what a particular case can tell us about a general claim. Let us consider the second question first.

      To determine if killing in itself (per se) is worse than letting die per se, the philosopher James Rachels asks us to imagine two different cases in which all factors are held constant except that one is a killing and the other a letting die. In the letting die case, someone sees a child drowning in a bathtub and does not rescue him because he intends the child’s death in order to inherit his money. In the killing case, someone holds a child in a bathtub under the water, drowning him, because he intends the child’s death in order to inherit his money.3 Rachels thinks that the killing case is not morally worse than the letting die case, and from this he concludes that killing is not per se morally worse than letting die per se.

      This claim that the moral character of different acts could differ per se, while some cases involving the different acts are morally equivalent, brings to mind (for different reasons) Wollheim’s remarks on Danto’s gallery of indiscernibles. The fact that in some cases it is impossible to distinguish an artwork perceptually from a non-artwork does not show that there is no per se (conceptual) difference based on perceptual properties between an artwork and a non-artwork. Given what I said about killing and letting die, it might be suggested that there is some factor in some cases that is overriding or “silencing” the role of certain factors that still make a per se difference between art and non-art.4

      In (B) I considered whether there is a moral difference in permissibility or in seriousness of a moral wrong. The most direct comparison with art bears on evaluation, whether some works of art are at least minimally good or why one is worse (or better) than another. Could, then, thought experiments be used in art as they are used to deal with