A Companion to Hobbes. Группа авторов

Читать онлайн.
Название A Companion to Hobbes
Автор произведения Группа авторов
Жанр Философия
Серия
Издательство Философия
Год выпуска 0
isbn 9781119635031



Скачать книгу

causal dependence on it, and everything that happens has something prior to it with which it causally coheres” (LS 1987, 337; see also LS 1987, 333; 389–90). Like Hobbes, the Stoics emphasize that the necessary connection applies to what they call “complete” or “sustaining” causes, i.e., “one during whose presence the effect remains and on whose removal the effect is effect is removed” (LS 1987, 336). As Hobbes later does, they derive from this conception of complete causality the principle that “where all the same circumstances obtain it is impossible that a result that does not ensue on one occasion should ensue on another” (LS 1987, 338). We call things “accidental” or “spontaneous” only because “there are causes hidden from our sight” (Plutarch, On Stoic Self Contradictions; In Sambursky 2014, 56). And they hold that all causal connections are by direct contact or through the medium of pneuma (Sambursky 2014, 54). As Hobbes later would, albeit from a more sophisticated and quantitative perspective, the Stoics perceived their necessitarian causal principles as required by their overall materialist cosmology: “the world would be wrenched apart and divided and no longer form a unity, forever governed by a single ordering and management, if an uncaused motion were introduced” (LS 1987, 337–8; see also Sambursky 2014, 130).18

      2.2.4 God

      Consider two passages. The first is Diogenes Laertius’ gloss of the role of God in Stoic physics:

      They believe there are two principles of the universe, the active and the passive. The passive is unqualified substance, i.e., matter, the active is the rational principle (logos) in it. i.e., God … In the beginning he was by himself and turned all substances into water via air and just as the seed is contained in the seminal fluid so this being the spermatic principle of the cosmos remains like this in the cosmos and makes the matter easy for itself to work with in the generation of subsequent things.

      The second is Hobbes’s (1662) account of his corporeal God’s operation in the world:

      I have seen, and so have many others, two waters, one of the river and the other mineral water, so that no man could discern one from the other from his sight; yet when they are both put together the whole substance could not be distinguished from milk. How then could the change be made in every part, but only by the activity of the mineral water, changing it everywhere to the sense and yet not being everywhere and in every part of the water. If such gross bodies have such great activity what then can we think of spirits, whose kinds be as many as there are kinds of liquor, and activity greater? Can it then be doubted that God, who is infinitely fine spirit, and withal intelligence, can make and change all species and kinds of bodies as he pleaseth?

      (EW IV.310)

      2.3 Conclusion

      Notes

      1 1 See also Leviathan XVI (2012, 244; 1651, 155), Leviathan XXIV (2012, 388; 1651, 190).

      2 2 Thomas Stanley’s influential History of Philosophy, devoted many chapters to Stoicism, including chapters on the corporeal God, the void and time (see Stanley 1655–1660, Vol. II, Part 8, 115–19, 123–4).

      3 3 De anima v (1885, 185): “The soul certainly sympathizes with the body, and shares in its pain, whenever it is injured by bruises, and wounds, and sores: the body, too, suffers with the soul, and is united with it (whenever it is afflicted with anxiety, distress, or love).” See also De anima vii (1885, 187).

      4 4