Free Speech. Jonathan Seglow

Читать онлайн.
Название Free Speech
Автор произведения Jonathan Seglow
Жанр Афоризмы и цитаты
Серия
Издательство Афоризмы и цитаты
Год выпуска 0
isbn 9781509526482



Скачать книгу

our interests qua listeners, readers and viewers; and our interests qua bystanders involuntarily affected by the speech of others (see Scanlon 1979). Bystanders’ interests become most relevant when we look at the harms produced by speech; but both speaker- and audience-based interests are especially relevant to the explanation of the value of speech, as we will now see.

      Mill develops a specific argument for free speech in chapter 2 of On Liberty. It is noteworthy that he does not set out his argument by employing the concept of harm, in other words by arguing that speech is harmless to others. His interest is instead in the special value of speech, which goes above that of ordinary liberty. This special value consists in the fact that speech is necessary for discovering the truth; and, in Mill’s view, knowing the truth is a source of happiness and well-being for both individuals and societies. Mill’s argument for free speech is therefore a consequentialist one; according to him, ‘[t]he truth of an opinion is part of its utility’ (Mill 2006, p. 29). This statement is best understood by considering Mill’s defence of liberty and free speech in his other famous work, Utilitarianism, produced a few years later, in 1863 (Mill 1998): there Mill argues that individuals’ actions, as well as the laws and policies of states, should be guided by the principle of maximising people’s happiness or utility.

      But what is really important for Mill is the process of discovery of more well-founded views. As independent-minded individuals employing our reasoning capacities together, we discuss and deliberate about what is most significant, persuasive, justifiable and so on in various fields. This is what serves our happiness as progressive beings – a happiness of a higher kind. In principle one could imagine an omniscient dictatorship, which used censorship and indoctrination to ensure that citizens hold only true or valid opinions and did so even as it curtailed free speech (Ten 1980). But such a ‘dictatorship of truth’ would possess no value for Mill, because in his eyes utility ultimately resides in people’s opportunity to employ their deliberative capacities. Robbed of this opportunity, citizens would not enjoy the practice of gradually arriving at more defensible views (cf. Brink 2008).

      Three specific arguments for free speech, all based on the discovery of truth, can be found in the pages of Mill’s long defence in On Liberty. First, he argues, free speech should be protected because otherwise some cogent or well-founded views would be silenced. As no one knows for sure which views those are, people who restrict the speech of others because they wrongly assume their own infallibility risk depriving themselves and others of the knowledge of silenced yet true opinions. This is often referred to as the infallibility argument. Among the many examples with which Mill illustrates it, that of Galileo Galilei (1564–1642) stands out as especially powerful. An early defender of heliocentrism, Galilei was forced by the Catholic Church to recant his views, which were considered heretical. This act of censorship, grounded in the Church’s assumption that it infallibly ‘knew’ that the sun revolves around the earth, delayed people’s appreciation of the scientific truth. More importantly, it deprived them of the utility that results from genuine knowledge of the universe and from the evaluation of that knowledge through their critical powers. Without free speech, the truth may take longer to emerge – if not fail to do so altogether.

      Third, Mill argues that the most defensible position on many subjects is frequently not captured by any single view but is instead shared among different ones. Each view is therefore partially correct, and hence it is important to allow as many opinions as possible to circulate in order for the full truth to emerge (Mill 2006, p. 55). Political parties, he argues, are among the clearest real-world manifestations of this process. More generally, the partial truth argument seems to be especially suitable for explaining the importance of free speech when it comes to moral and political issues, where disagreement is generally the norm, as opposed for example to scientific matters, where the truth often is, indeed, all on one side.

      While Mill does not emphasise, in On Liberty, the ways in which speech can harm, he does not overlook them either. In a famous passage, he writes:

      An opinion that corn-dealers are starvers of the poor, or that private property is robbery, ought to be unmolested when simply circulated through the press, but may justly incur punishment when delivered orally to an excited mob assembled before the house of a corn-dealer, or when handed about among the same mob in the form of a placard. (Mill 2006, p. 64)

      Other restrictions consistent with Mill’s doctrine concern forms of