Critique of Rights. Christoph Menke

Читать онлайн.
Название Critique of Rights
Автор произведения Christoph Menke
Жанр Афоризмы и цитаты
Серия
Издательство Афоризмы и цитаты
Год выпуска 0
isbn 9781509520428



Скачать книгу

claim that a person or “subject” can make which is normatively binding or, as Kant puts it, the “moral capacity for putting others under obligations.”12

      None of the modern authors who distinguished between right as law [Gesetz] and right as claim considered this distinction to be a new conceptual insight. Indeed, for the most part they never even maintained that a terminological innovation was involved. They instead presented the distinction as though it were already established by Roman legal practice or by Aristotelian-Scholastic legal theory. Yet such a distinction had never been made explicitly in practice or in theory, prior to modern legal thought. The distinction between right and a right, between law and right,13 between right [Recht] as law [Gesetz] and right as claim, “right” [Recht] in the objective and in the subjective sense, seems as ancient as it is modern: ancient in what it says, in its content; but modern to the extent that it is said, that this content is explicitly formulated and established. On the one hand, it seems as if the distinction between right as law and right as claim is always already given. On the other hand, to make this distinction is to do something fundamentally new, with far-reaching consequences. In other words, this distinction is more rhetorically than semantically novel, more an act of distinguishing than an issue of content. In that case, however, can it still be the same distinction?

      Because Hobbes was the first to distinguish with incomparable clarity between “right” and “law,” in such a way that he sought to prove the State as primarily founded on “right,” of which “law” is a mere consequence [ ….] – Hobbes is for that very reason the founder of modern political philosophy.17

      Strauss’ historical argument for Hobbes as the original author of the distinction between law and right [Anspruch] is thus based on his thesis concerning the point of this distinction: the reason for making it is to “subordinate law to right.”18

      Regardless of what we think about Strauss’ suggested chronology, it forms the systematic substance of his interpretation of Hobbes. In distinguishing law and right [Anspruch], we are thus concerned with nothing less than a new response to the question of priority, and hence with the question of basis: at issue is “the supplanting of the primacy of obligation [C.M. – which the law imposes] by the primacy of claim.”19 By isolating the claim [Anspruch] in this manner, over and against obligation and law, it becomes the “fundamental moral fact” prior to law.20 According to Strauss, this therefore means that modern politics begins by drawing the distinction between law and claim. To make this distinction is the modern act of revolution: “The fundamental change from an orientation by natural duties to an orientation by natural rights.”21

      But how can there be a legal claim that is able to normatively bind others before and thus independent of law’s legal order? Is not the idea of a right before law “nonsense upon stilts,”26 as Jeremy Bentham said of the rights of man, or, as Raymond Geuss puts it, “white magic”?27

      Along with Strauss, Hans Kelsen has also objected to the concept of rights, arguing that liberalism establishes a “dualism” – of claim and law – which supposedly reverses the explanatory relations between them:

      The original intention of the dualism of objective and subjective right [Recht] expresses the thought that the latter precedes the former both logically and temporally: subjective rights emerge first (such as private property, the primary prototype of a subjective right), and only later do we also find objective right as a state order that protects, recognizes, and secures the subjective rights that have emerged independently from it.28

      Subjective right precedes objective right, the claim precedes law. For Kelsen, this basic thesis of liberal dualism has an obvious “ideological function”: it is supposed “to conceal the socio-economically decisive function” of capitalist private property.29 However, the priority of claim over law is also conceptually incoherent. It encapsulates the aporia of modern natural law [Naturrechts] that lies at the basis of liberal dualism: the paradox of a natural legal claim – the idea of a claim that is supposed to naturally occur of its own accord and at the same time is supposed to be obligatory.

      The idea of a natural right [Rechts] is paradoxical because it is the idea of a right [Rechts] before law [Recht]. “Rights before law,” however, either (i) are not rights at all, or (ii) do not really exist before law at all.

      [Everyone] always endeavors as far as in him lies to preserve his own being and (since every man has right to the extent that he has power), whether he be wise or ignorant, whatever he endeavors and does, he endeavors and does by the sovereign right of Nature. From this it follows that Nature’s right and established order under which all men are born and for the most part live, forbids only those things that no one desires and no one can do.30

      “There is no normativity in nature,”31 and for this reason, too, there are no natural rights.

      (ii) Or the following is valid: if rights are supposed