Critique of Rights. Christoph Menke

Читать онлайн.
Название Critique of Rights
Автор произведения Christoph Menke
Жанр Афоризмы и цитаты
Серия
Издательство Афоризмы и цитаты
Год выпуска 0
isbn 9781509520428



Скачать книгу

subjects to refuse such a command – although determining what is just and unjust is up to the sovereign alone.

      This insight into the structure of sovereignty has two implications for law [Recht], the most important medium of authority [Herrschaft]. First, law is defined negatively, as a being-free-to or a being-permitted-to: law can never forbid subjects from striving for their self-preservation, which it must always allow or accept. This is the other side of the positive authorization of the natural by the modern character of rights, which we have already examined (see chapter 2). The internalization of the natural in law, the opening of law to the natural, is here understood to mean that the natural power of self-preservation forms the goal of law: law is intended to enable the interest of subjects, to enable their striving for self-preservation. This obviously includes the power to define and restrict their interest (so that everyone has equal opportunity). At the same time, however, it should now be evident that legal power has its fundamental limit, its unreachable counterpart, in the interest or striving for self-preservation: it must assume that this striving is a fact and allow it.

      Second, this means that the legal system distinguishes between the striving for self-preservation – which is always allowed – and its fulfillment – which law [Recht] must always restrict. The sovereign may not demand that a human being violate his own law [Gesetz], the nature of his striving or volition – that he turn his will against himself or turn himself against his will “in such a way that he ceases to be a human being.”42 This means, however, nothing less than that the sovereign should not interfere at all in its subjects’ volition if it does not wish to end up contradicting itself, to end up contradicting why it was established and its justification. What the sovereign’s subjects wish and strive for, and how they do this, is their concern, since it is a natural matter – the kind of natural fact that constitutes the basis because it is the starting point for the creation of the sovereign. The natural, the striving for self-preservation, which the sovereign must authorize because he is authorized by it, therefore becomes internality, which systematically eludes his rule. The interior of the sovereign’s subjects is external to law and therefore law must remain external to it. Permission of the natural signifies law’s self-restriction in the face of internality and thereby its restriction of itself to exteriority.

      From whence may be concluded this first point, that they to whom God hath not spoken immediately, are to receive the positive commandments of God, from their Soveraign … And consequently in every Common-wealth, they who have no supernaturall Revelation to the contrary, ought to obey the laws of their own Soveraign, in the externall acts and profession of Religion. As for the inward thought, and beleef of men, which humane Governours can take no notice of, (for God onely knoweth the heart) they are not voluntary, nor the effect of the laws, but of the unrevealed will, and of the power of God; and consequently fall not under obligation.43

      This line of thought clearly aims to distinguish the inner (thought or belief) from the outer (actions and declarations). The sovereign must regulate the latter and prescribe or forbid, in order to fulfill the goal that forms its raison d’être: protection, peace, defending everyone. Conversely, the sovereign is not supposed to regulate the former, to impose or forbid thought or belief, because he cannot do this. Deviating from the architecture of his theory, Hobbes nevertheless argues, on epistemological grounds, that the sovereign cannot do this (because thought or belief cannot be perceived by a human ruler), which he goes on to give a theological twist (because thought or belief can only be perceived by a divine ruler).44 Yet the actual Hobbesian argument for the claim that the sovereign cannot and should not regulate his subjects’ internality, their thoughts and beliefs, is precisely the same one that he makes for the claim that the sovereign must regulate their exteriority, their actions and declarations. The sovereign’s incapacity is not epistemological, but a matter of legitimacy, and thus essential. A consequence of this is that legitimacy, and thereby the essence of the sovereign, consists in the sovereign’s legalization of the extra-legal, which it must simultaneously preserve and protect (in positive terms) and leave alone and put up with (in negative terms).

      In his study of Hobbes’ Leviathan, with its juxtaposition of anti-Semitic resentment and brilliant insights, Carl Schmitt has called the divergence between a legally regulated exterior and a legally unregulated interior the “seed of death” for the sovereign as conceived by Hobbes himself in the image of the Leviathan.45 As soon as this divergence occurs, all it takes, according to Schmitt, is “a small intellectual switch emanating from the nature of Jewish life”46 to bring about the bourgeois liberal constitutional state:

      The self-restriction