Название | Contemporary Mind - Some Modern Answers |
---|---|
Автор произведения | J. W. N. Sullivan |
Жанр | Философия |
Серия | |
Издательство | Философия |
Год выпуска | 0 |
isbn | 9781528784955 |
Assuming, however, that time is a reality, what are we to say about the question of human immortality? If we regard the mind as an aspect of the body, as being one form of its activities, then, of course, immortality is out of the question. We can only raise the question of immortality if we regard the mind as capable of existing independently of the body. This hypothesis is less easy to entertain than it was formerly. Our present physiological knowledge shows a much closer correlation between mental states and bodily changes than was before suspected. Both intelligence and character can, it appears, be fundamentally affected by suitable operations on the body. Even if these results lead us to believe that an indissoluble connection exists between mind and body, we are not thereby compelled, of course, to accept materialism. We are not forced to believe that the mind is identical with the body, or with any part of it. Indeed, the reduction of mind to matter remains as unintelligible as it ever was. But this fact is of no value for the hypothesis of immortality if we suppose that the nature of the mind-body connection, whatever it may be, is such that the mind cannot exist independently of the body. As there is nothing that forces us to make this assumption, we will not make it, but will consider what can be said for and against the hypothesis of human immortality on a priori grounds.
An argument against human immortality, which C. D. Broad, in his magnificent book on The Mind and its Place in Nature, rightly says has great influence on feeling, is the apparent random, wasteful, careless manner in which human beings come into the world. Besides the fact that so many human beings come into the world so casually, the result of a passing caprice or, perhaps, of a drunken frolic, we have to consider those that are born dead, are born idiotic, or horribly malformed. We have also to consider such indefensible abortions as Siamese twins and worse monsters. It would seem that, at best, Nature is utterly indifferent, and operates entirely without regard for human notions of beauty and dignity. It is difficult to believe that the slobbering and misshapen idiot, bom of a drab in a ditch, is animated by an immortal soul.
The first part of this argument, that based on the casual way in which many human beings come into the world, need not have much weight with those who believe that life forms part of some great scheme. For we do not know what unimaginable combination of forces and events may have been necessary to produce what seems to us a casual incident. Also, we cannot argue the triviality of an effect from the apparent triviality of its cause. A forest fire may be started by a casual match. We could also suppose that the apparent cause is only part of the real cause. The physical coupling of two human beings, whether casual or deliberate, may be only part of what is required for the creation of a new mind. But the second part of the argument, that based upon the apparent unworthiness of so many human beings to survive, has wider ramifications. For if we deny immortality to some human beings, where are we to draw the line? If a certain level of intelligence and character is necessary for survival, how do we know what this level is? Might it not be that no human mind has yet appeared which reaches the required level? And if we adopt the other alternative and say that all human beings are immortal, where again are we to draw the line? It would appear that we must include not only the least developed races now existing, but also primitive man. Thus we would be led by insensible gradations to include the higher apes and, finally, shell-fish, microscopic organisms, and plants. The conclusion seems to be absurd.
Dr. Broad, who has given careful attention to this argument, thinks that there is very little in it. The argument, put simply, has three forms, (1) Oysters are not immortal; (2) We pass, by a series of insensible gradations, from oysters to men; (3) Therefore men are not immortal.
Now, in the first place, however gradual the transition from oysters to men may be, it must be admitted that there is a very great difference between these two ends of the chain. Men differ, in very important respects, from oysters. Now are those characteristics of oysters which make us deny them immortality characteristics which differentiate oysters markedly from men? If they are, then the argument from continuity proves nothing, for it is the differences that are important. Now when we reflect on our reasons for denying immortality to oysters we shall find, Dr. Broad thinks, that they are concerned with aspects where the oyster is markedly non-human. We may instance the feebleness of the oyster’s mind, the poverty of his spiritual nature, the apparent triviality of his earthly destiny. It is because of these differences from his human successor that we are inclined to deny immortality to the oyster. The fact that there is continuity between the oyster and man, therefore, is quite compatible with the assertion that men are immortal and that oysters are not. If we accept this assertion, then the utmost the argument from continuity can do is to make us doubtful of the immortality of some intermediate types. We might hesitate, for example, about kangaroos.
The direction of the argument from continuity can, of course, be reversed. We can argue from the probable immortality of man to the less probable immortality of the oyster. The apparent absurdity of this argument seems to spring, not only from the characteristics of oysters, but also from their numbers. It is felt that the survival of every living creature is unlikely, if only on the ground that such vast numbers would be involved. But, as Dr. Broad says, we have no reason to suppose that the universe is conducted according to the Law of Parsimony. Indeed, we have very good evidence that it is not. The progress of astronomy was hindered by the fact that the Copernican theory, when its consequences were looked into, required the stars to be separated from one another by enormous distances. Astronomers of that day, unconsciously deriving their notions of the probabilities from farming considerations, could not believe that such a great waste of space was incurred. We now know that such notions of probability afford no clue to the structure of the universe. Nature shows no disposition to avoid large numbers.
There seems to be no conclusive argument against the immortality of man. Are there any good arguments for it? We may dismiss the arguments based on metaphysical principles and on ethical considerations, since it is generally agreed that they have failed. The immortality of man cannot be established on a priori grounds. We have to ask, therefore, whether there is any empirical evidence for it. This is a difficult question to answer, for we find, when we come to examine the evidence that has been put forth, that our estimate of it is influenced by notions of probability that may be altogether irrelevant. Many of the messages supposed to be received from discarnate spirits at spiritualistic séances, for instance, seem so crude, undignified, and downright silly, that they seem to bear evidence of their falseness on their face. Quite apart from other considerations, we reject them without further examination. But it may be that our notions about the spirit world are altogether too exalted. It may be that the shock of death reduces even the greatest human minds to a condition of relative imbecility, that an educated man forgets practically all he knows, and that a great poet becomes indistinguishable from the more insipid composers of Christmas card verses. The evidence adduced by spiritualists, if we take it seriously, certainly seems to point to this conclusion, and if we reject this evidence it must be on a priori grounds. We must be convinced that the universe is not as evil, or, at least, as imbecile, as the spiritualists would have us believe. But it is difficult to find any grounds that would justify this conviction. Why should we assume that the nature of the universe is consonant with our higher aspirations? We know, from our experience, that these aspirations are often defeated. There is sufficient evil in the world to make us doubt whether the general trend of things is towards good. Millions of men, for thousands of years, have found it perfectly consonant with their experience of the way the universe is governed to suppose that a hell forms part of its constitution, that an eternity