A Companion to Hobbes. Группа авторов

Читать онлайн.
Название A Companion to Hobbes
Автор произведения Группа авторов
Жанр Философия
Серия
Издательство Философия
Год выпуска 0
isbn 9781119635031



Скачать книгу

of writers on physics and morals that geometry and arithmetic are the only mathematical ones” (Hobbes 1973 [1642–1643], 106; 1976 [1642–1643], 24). Indeed, in Anti-White Hobbes does not identify natural philosophy as mixed mathematics, including only astronomy, mechanics, optics, and music in a list (Hobbes 1973 [1642–1643], 106; 1976 [1642–1643], 24). It is not until 15 years later in De homine, reflecting backward upon his own work in De corpore, that Hobbes declares that “true physics” is mixed mathematics. This is speculative, but had Hobbes arrived at this connection earlier, it would have made more sense to include the De homine II–IX within De corpore Part IV rather than within the second section of the Elementa. For the present discussion, Hobbes’s optics is of interest because of what it shows about Hobbes’s understanding of the relationship between geometry and explanations of natural phenomena.

      Hobbes based his optics upon what he called the “visual line” and a claim that distinct vision occurs through the optic axis, i.e., the line through which rays from an external object strike the eye perpendicularly and then, after hitting the retina, reflect back outward from the eye by following the same line on which they entered. This line moving back outward is the visual line, which Hobbes defines in Minute as “the line wherein any point in the object shall appeare” (1983 [1646], 336). Only rays traveling through the optic axis will generate distinct vision, and he declares that vision outside the optic axis will be “confused and feeble” (OL II.14). This is why it is necessary when perceiving an object in motion, or even a very large object, for human perceivers to move their eyes or turn their head. In moving their eyes or their head, perceivers’ tracking movements keep the parts of an external object within their optic axis, making distinct vision possible.

      These two foundational components to Hobbes’s optics – the visual line and the optic axis – are present in Hobbes’s Minute of 1646 (1983), which pre-dates De homine. However, in the De homine rendition of these ideas Hobbes now has available his own geometry from De corpore Part III, and he provides citations to geometrical principles from it. He uses these geometrical principles in De homine II to explain the apparent location of external objects with reference to the optic axis. Hobbes saw his account of the apparent location of objects as what differentiated his optics from others; indeed, he claimed in Minute that others working in optics had failed sufficiently to focus on apparent locations of objects and had instead focused on the “place of the Image” (1983 [1646], 335). An additional foundational component to Hobbes’s optics (discussed later) is that sensation generally, of which vision is one kind, is caused by pressure propagated through media and that when a human perceiver’s body is affected by pressure from external objects their body will resist that pressure. This resistance from the perceiver’s body will reflect that pressure outward, similar to how light reflects after shining on a mirror. That outward reflection generates distinct vision when the pressure inward occurs in the optic axis and results in “confused and feeble” vision when not.

      Hobbes appeals to a second geometrical principle in De homine II, this time to explain why vision that occurs by means of a ray striking the eye obliquely, i.e., outside the optic axis, will result in an object’s apparent location not matching its actual location. This time he borrows and cites a geometrical principle from De corpore XXII.6 that establishes that when some body A presses against body B, without penetrating the body B, body A will “recede in a straight line perpendicular to its superficies in that point in which it was pressed” (EW I.336). Although Hobbes holds that rays entering the eye obliquely will be refracted through the humors inside the eye toward the center of that organ, they will ultimately strike the retina in a different place compared to rays entering through the optic axis. As a result, he claims that when reflecting from the retina and continuing out of the eye, the visual line for such an object will present its apparent location as different from its actual location. In terms of Figure 4.3, the ray from object I strikes the eye obliquely and ultimately hits the retina at N. Given the principle from De corpore XXII.6, the ray reflects from the surface of the retina perpendicularly, which results in the apparent location of object I being along the line from N to E.

      4.3 Hobbesian Natural Philosophy: Sense in De Corpore XXV

      Hobbes had a keen interest in understanding human sensation, especially since he held that all ideas began in whole or in part in sense. His discussion of sense in Leviathan 1 is well known, but Hobbes himself states that what he offers there is not so much an explanation on its own but rather has been provided to prevent there being a gap in the account offered in Leviathan:

      To know the cause of naturall Sense, is not very necessary to the business now in hand; and I have written else-where of the same at large. Nevertheless, to fill each part of my present method, I will deliver the same in this place.

      (2012, 22; 1651, 3)

      Hobbes may have had Elements of Law in mind with this reference to what had been “written else-where,” or perhaps he had the explanation offered in De corpore XXV that would be published later (as Malcolm notes; see 2012, 23 fn. a). Regardless, the explanation that Hobbes provides in De corpore XXV will be the focus of this section because, just as in the case from De homine examined above, in that chapter Hobbes provides an explicit citation to a principle