A Companion to Hobbes. Группа авторов

Читать онлайн.
Название A Companion to Hobbes
Автор произведения Группа авторов
Жанр Философия
Серия
Издательство Философия
Год выпуска 0
isbn 9781119635031



Скачать книгу

philosophy with geometrical procedures, they cannot account for a moral science in Hobbes’s sense. 2a) also excludes physics from science. 2b) holds that Hobbes maintains the possibility of scientifically deducing a consistent body of theoretical and practical knowledge from first principles but includes alternative starting points and methods for non-philosophers to gain knowledge of practical philosophy.17 This too is promising, but to the extent that there is one method, it is an ideal that does no work. In practice, Hobbes proceeds as though physics and politics are independent domains with their own methods.

      Despite these problems, 2) is better supported than 1). Hobbes’s view of scientific knowledge and generic definition of method point to one type of cognitive activity that constitutes scientific knowledge of all philosophical subjects. Regardless of whether one studies natural or artificial bodies, starts from cognitions of causes or effects, formal definitions or true cognitions attained by introspection, the process of methodical computation that charts the shortest route between causes and effects should be identical. This fits Hobbes’s aim of inaugurating a civil science to exorcise the Scholastic philosophy Empusa. Absent a unity of method for science, the boundaries between practical philosophy and religion will blur as non-scientific forms of cognition can then be invoked to confuse the rights and duties of subjects. Hobbes’s approach to identifying and removing the source of civil strife then falls apart. Hence overall 2) is the correct approach. I now draw on Hobbes’s context to propose a third variation, 2c).

      1.3 Analyses and Syntheses Reinterpreted in Context

      the cause of some certain phenomena, or to at least discover something certain, such as whatever would be the cause of light, heat, heaviness, a proposed shape, and similar things; or in which subject a certain proposed accident would inhere, or for the purpose of a certain effect which is proposed to be generated from many accidents, which [ones] would conduce most powerfully towards it; or in which manner for the producing of a certain effect, the proposed particular causes ought to be conjoined. On account of this variety of things sought, sometimes the Analytic method, sometimes the Synthetic, and sometimes both is to be summoned.

      (Hobbes 1999, 59; OL I.60–1)

      Hobbes later gives two examples to illustrate the strictly analytical method that yields the universal notions we need to attain unqualified knowledge of things. Both begin with an idea, from experience, as when we see something approaching, but now resolved from less general to more:

      1 My idea of this square is resolved or analyzed into “plain, terminated with a certain number of equal and straight lines and right angles.” I can then resolve or analyze these concepts further into the properties common to all material objects: “line,” “plane,” “angle,” “straightness.”

      2 My conception of gold is resolved into ideas of “solid,” “visible,” “heavy,” I can then further resolve or analyze these ideas into successively more general ones, like “extension” and “corporeity” until I arrive at the most general one: motion.

      Once you have analyzed down to the most general, also the simplest, conceptual elements of your ideas you will have the causes of individual concepts of a square and gold. Hobbes’s use of the term “cause” suggests that the resolution of gold is a mechanistic reduction into the physical parts of gold. For how can concepts cause our ideas? However, Hobbes uses “cause” in the Aristotelian sense of one or more explanatory factors, since he also claims that