Название | Education for Life |
---|---|
Автор произведения | George Turnbull |
Жанр | Философия |
Серия | Natural Law and Enlightenment Classics |
Издательство | Философия |
Год выпуска | 0 |
isbn | 9781614872641 |
[print edition page xxii]
in the natural law tradition of the methodological unity of the two main branches of philosophy, and there is little doubt about Turnbull’s debt to Grotius, Pufendorf, and Richard Cumberland in this regard. Nevertheless, his 1723 thesis struck a new note when he appealed to Query 31 of Newton’s Opticks to justify his claim that the moral realm ought to be investigated empirically using the methods of analysis and synthesis.54 Turnbull was thus an early promoter of the Newtonian form of scientism adopted by successive generations of moralists not only in Aberdeen but throughout the European Enlightenment more generally.55
Like the Edinburgh virtuosi who shaped the early Scottish Enlightenment, Turnbull believed that all branches of human learning formed a coherent and unified system which he likened to a tree of knowledge.56 This view underwrote his belief in the methodological unity of the natural and moral sciences, and it also enabled him to delineate the cognitive relations between his historical and antiquarian interests and his broader philosophical concerns. His fascination with history and Roman antiquities was something that he probably originally shared with his fellow Rankenian Charles Mackie. At Edinburgh (and elsewhere) history was taught as an adjunct to law, so that for Turnbull and Mackie the study of these subjects was closely intertwined.57 Once Turnbull became a travelling tutor his taste for “the Study of the Antients” deepened, while his contacts with antiquarians and historians in London turned his researches in new directions.58 His work on antiquities and history was also deeply influenced by French models, as seen in his Three Dissertations and his edition of Justin.59 These late works register his indebtedness to the critical scholarship championed
[print edition page xxiii]
by the Parisian Académie des Inscriptions et Belles-Lettres and to the rationale for the study of history articulated by the noted historian and pedagogue Charles Rollin. The Three Dissertations pays tribute to Richard Mead’s collection: one of the engravings Turnbull included illustrates the celebrated ancient painting owned by Mead that was taken to portray Augustus, Agrippa, Maecenas, and Horace, while the other depicts a bas relief of actors and a musician that had recently been uncovered in Rome, which Turnbull believed was worthy of Mead’s ownership.60 Two of the three essays which he translated from the Histoire et mémoires de l’Académie des inscriptions et belles lettres discussed antiquarian topics related to these engravings. The third described the notable collection of paintings and statues amassed in ancient Rome by the infamous Gaius Verres. Turnbull used this essay as a vehicle to state what he believed were the proper ends of collecting the remains of the past. According to Turnbull, true collectors like Mead sought to benefit the public by opening up their cabinets to foster “the ambition to excel in the Arts of Design” and to promote “the Study of polite Literature” among their fellow citizens. But in Britain their efforts to arouse the “natural Genius” of the nation were sadly hampered by the lack of institutions comparable to the state and provincial academies in France. Turnbull here echoed a common complaint among men of letters that the British government did far too little to foster the advancement of learning.61
Turnbull’s discussion of the value of historical knowledge in the preface to his edition of Justin’s History complements his extended treatment of the topic in his Observations upon Liberal Education.62 As in the Observations, he paid tribute to Rollin’s achievements as a historian and apologist for the study of history and, following Rollin and the humanist tradition, emphasized that historical knowledge is valuable insofar as it can be used to teach moral and political lessons.63 This view of the primarily didactic
[print edition page xxiv]
function of history—what has come to be known as “exemplar history”—is encapsulated in Lord Bolingbroke’s dictum “that history is philosophy teaching by examples how to conduct ourselves in all the situations of private and public life.”64 For Turnbull civil history was thus the grounding for ethics and politics just as natural history was for natural philosophy. Moreover, he insisted that the facts of both branches of history illustrate broader moral and religious principles, and it was the recognition that the facts serve such higher ends that for him distinguished the true historian and antiquary from those who were guilty of mere “cockle-shellship,” that is, the random stockpiling of objects and information with no eye for their meaning.65
Turnbull’s Treatise on Ancient Painting explored another facet of his tree of knowledge, namely the connection between philosophy and oratory, poetry, and painting. His discussion hinged on his claim that painting is a language that can be employed to express the truths discovered in the moral and natural sciences. Painting can thus play a role in a liberal education akin to that of history, for paintings can illustrate the workings of natural laws and moral principles and hence serve as “Samples or Experiments” of those laws and principles.66 In the selections reprinted below, however, we see that his main aim in the Treatise was not simply to justify the study of classical art. Rather, his reflections on the uses of the fine arts in education were the starting point for a general exposition of his pedagogical ideals, which he claimed mirrored those of the leading moralists of ancient Greece and Rome. This claim masked the extent to which his views on education reflected his own experiences as a pedagogue as well as his reading of more
[print edition page xxv]
recent educational tracts.67 His belief that education ought to foster the cultivation of both private and public moral and political virtue could be traced back to the ancients, but it had also been forcefully enunciated by Shaftesbury and Molesworth in their calls for educational reform.68 Furthermore, Turnbull’s remarks on the educational rationale for foreign travel owed more to Molesworth’s preface to An Account of Denmark than to the writings of Greek or Roman authors.69 And although he credited the ancients with the map of learning that justified his scheme for a liberal education, his conception of a unified system of the arts and sciences was in fact the creation of modern thinkers and was something that he shared with fellow exponents of Enlightenment.70 In effect, the Treatise provided the ancient precedents for a thoroughly modern plan for a liberal education, and Turnbull’s deployment of erudition in the service of pedagogical reform illustrates how classical antiquity was used to underwrite Enlightenment in eighteenth-century Europe.
Who, then, was George Turnbull? His life fits the pattern of the “Scotsman on the make” seeking a career in London and exploiting the opportunities opened up by the Union of 1707.71 His ideas and values were those of the virtuosi who