Название | The Socratic Turn |
---|---|
Автор произведения | Dustin Sebell |
Жанр | Афоризмы и цитаты |
Серия | Haney Foundation Series |
Издательство | Афоризмы и цитаты |
Год выпуска | 0 |
isbn | 9780812292244 |
However that may be, the young Socrates’ vacillation as to the nature of the body (“blood” or “air” or “fire”) responsible for thought or knowledge in human beings (96b4) was very different from his wavering as to whether what was responsible for this was in fact “none of these things, but the brain” (96b4–5). For his wavering pertained in the first case to the nature of the matter (“blood” or “air” or “fire”) by virtue of which the compounds made out of it (“we [human beings]”) acquire a characteristic or power of their very own (“who are thoughtful”). In the second case, however, he vacillated as to this: whether that matter—whatever its nature or form may be—which gives to the compounds made out of it (human beings) some characteristic or power of their very own (thought or knowledge) is to be regarded as a whole in its own right (as “the brain” is); or whether, insofar as it is the matter (that is, “the blood”) of the very matter in question (“the brain”) that does this, that matter too (“the brain”) is to be regarded as a mere compound.
These examples of the two kinds of vacillation or wavering that Socrates was liable to as a young natural scientist, the only ones he specifies here, have far-reaching implications. Indeed, if they did not have sources embedded in natural science itself they would have no place here. Still, it remains to be seen what those might be. It will have to suffice for now to assert, and as we proceed to bear the possibility in mind, that while the first kind of vacillation will prove to stem from one of the difficulties that eventually made Socrates turn away from natural science, the second will prove to stem from another difficulty.
Natural Science at a Glance
After having cast a shadow of doubt over the possibility of natural science, Socrates gives a brief report of the makeup of the examinations entailed by it. But in keeping with the fact that their results remained uncertain or merely tentative, Socrates presents those examinations in the form of unanswered questions. What he says to begin with is that as a young natural scientist he examined “first” (96b1) the cause or causes through which animals come to be in general (96b2–3), and through which thoughtfulness (96b4) or knowledge (96b5–9) comes to be in human beings in particular. He expected to find the cause or causes which organize the animals, in all their complexity, in a specific blend of nonliving things or bodies (“some putrefaction”), on one hand, and the mindless changes or motions to which they are subject (“the hot and the cold”), on the other. As for how human beings, alone of all animals, come to be thoughtful, he expected to find the cause or causes of this in one or another simple body or matter (“blood” or “air” or “fire”). But as an alternative to this (96b4–5) he wondered whether it was not in fact some other more complex body or matter out of which our thought or knowledge comes into being (“the brain”). Then or “in turn,” after having examined in this manner the coming to be of these things, the young Socrates examined their perishing, too, presumably into the very matter from which they originally came to be (96b9). Finally, as if by the way, he adds that he examined the qualities of heaven and earth too (96b9–c1).
And with that addition, the objects of the young Socrates’ examinations, as he presents them here, fall into a certain order. Animals in general and human beings in particular depend on heaven and earth, which must be there before the former can come to be and which may perhaps remain even after they perish (Laws 889b1–d4). If the young Socrates examined each thing in light of its roots, and the roots of each thing in light of its roots, and so on, he would have been naturally led in the end from the examination of the coming to be and perishing of animals and human beings to the examination of heaven and earth. As the comprehensive and perhaps eternal order within which those transitory things come and go, heaven and earth would have soon become the favored objects of a young natural scientist’s examinations. And yet, precisely if this is so, the fact that Socrates gives to the favored objects of his youthful examinations such slight attention here must come as a surprise. But his reserve is clarified by and it clarifies in turn exactly what it was that, as a young natural scientist, he thought about the roots of (the qualities of) heaven and earth. For reserve would have been called for if Socrates, in his youth, thought such things about the whole or its roots as were at odds with piety.5 And had the young Socrates ascribed to the roots of heaven and earth the same soulless, mindless, or “Epimethean” (Protagoras 320c6ff., 361c2–d5) character he evidently ascribed to everything else—including even “soul” itself (96b4, 96b5–9)6—would his outlook not have been an impious one?7 How can blind necessities (108e5–109a2) such as “vortex” (99b7) or “air” (99b8) truly replace Zeus as “king”?8 Now, Socrates has already admitted, in effect, that the impression he gave at his trial, that is, that he was never, “ever” engaged in natural science, was a misleading one (Apology 19a8–d6). But has the report of his engagement with it that he allows himself to give here not also served to corroborate or confirm Meletus’ allegation that at some point in the past, if not also at present, he did not believe that the sun and the moon are gods but rather that the sun is stone and the moon is earth (Apology 26d1–e3)?
Be that as it may, was not the long-standing tradition of reflection, “which they call inquiry concerning nature,” that the young Socrates was, for a time, only carrying on without modification itself vulnerable to this allegation? Socrates himself was fully aware that it was widely believed at any rate that all who philosophize, or who investigate “the things aloft and under the earth,” do not believe in gods (Apology 18b4–c4, 23d2–7, 26d1–9). He even seems to have believed this of “the wise” himself (Phaedrus 229b4–d1, compare Apology 18b4–c4 as well as Phaedo 61b2–7 and Euthyphro 6a7–10)! The Athenian stranger in Plato’s Laws speaks of these matters more openly perhaps but also, to compensate for this, more harshly. To all those engaged in “investigations concerning nature,” he attributes disbelief (Laws 891c7–d3), as well as the conviction that the earth, sun, moon, and stars are not gods and divine things but rather “earth and stones, incapable of thinking about human affairs” (Laws 886d1–e2, 889b1–e5).9 He even goes so far as to say that “everything that moves in heaven and that appears to the eyes appeared to [those who philosophize] to be full of stones and earth and many other soulless bodies, which provided the causes of the entire cosmos,” and that these things “caused many varieties of atheism and other disgusting views to infect such men” (Laws 967c2–d7). Whether those who philosophize warrant this objection, assuming that it is in fact an objection, is not yet certain. But, if they do, some light would be cast on Socrates’ earlier remark to the effect that as a young man he was attracted to natural science at least in part because it seemed to him “magnificent” to possess it.10
The Certainty of Natural Science
It